Product Code Database
Example Keywords: mmorpg -digital $86-131
   » » Wiki: Choice Function
Tag Wiki 'Choice Function'.
Tag

Let X be a set of sets none of which are empty. Then a choice function ( selector, selection) on X is a mathematical function f that is defined on X such that f is a mapping that assigns each element of X to one of its elements.


An example
Let X = { {1,4,7}, {9}, {2,7} }. Then the function f defined by f({1, 4, 7}) = 7, f({9}) = 9 and f({2, 7}) = 2 is a choice function on X.


History and importance
(1904) introduced choice functions as well as the axiom of choice (AC) and proved the well-ordering theorem, which states that every set can be . AC states that every set of nonempty sets has a choice function. A weaker form of AC, the axiom of countable choice (ACω) states that every of nonempty sets has a choice function. However, in the absence of either AC or ACω, some sets can still be shown to have a choice function.

  • If X is a set of nonempty sets, then one can construct a choice function for X by picking one element from each member of X. This requires only finitely many choices, so neither AC or ACω is needed.
  • If every member of X is a nonempty set, and the union \bigcup X is well-ordered, then one may choose the least element of each member of X. In this case, it was possible to simultaneously well-order every member of X by making just one choice of a well-order of the union, so neither AC nor ACω was needed. (This example shows that the well-ordering theorem implies AC. The converse is also true, but less trivial.)


Choice function of a multivalued map
Given two sets X and Y, let F be a multivalued map from X to Y (equivalently, F:X\rightarrow\mathcal{P}(Y) is a function from X to the of Y).

A function f: X \rightarrow Y is said to be a selection of F, if:

\forall x \in X \, ( f(x) \in F(x) ) \,.

The existence of more regular choice functions, namely continuous or measurable selections is important in the theory of differential inclusions, , and mathematical economics.

(1989). 9780521265645, Cambridge University Press.
See Selection theorem.


Bourbaki tau function
used for their foundations that had a \tau symbol that could be interpreted as choosing an object (if one existed) that satisfies a given proposition. So if P(x) is a predicate, then \tau_{x}(P) is one particular object that satisfies P (if one exists, otherwise it returns an arbitrary object). Hence we may obtain quantifiers from the choice function, for example P( \tau_{x}(P)) was equivalent to (\exists x)(P(x)).
(1968). 9780201006346, Hermann.

However, Bourbaki's choice operator is stronger than usual: it's a global choice operator. That is, it implies the axiom of global choice.John Harrison, "The Bourbaki View" eprint. Hilbert realized this when introducing epsilon calculus."Here, moreover, we come upon a very remarkable circumstance, namely, that all of these transfinite axioms are derivable from a single axiom, one that also contains the core of one of the most attacked axioms in the literature of mathematics, namely, the axiom of choice: A(a)\to A(\varepsilon(A)), where \varepsilon is the transfinite logical choice function." Hilbert (1925), “On the Infinite”, excerpted in Jean van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel, p. 382. From nCatLab.


See also
  • Axiom of countable choice
  • Axiom of dependent choice
  • Hausdorff paradox


Notes
Page 1 of 1
1
Page 1 of 1
1

Account

Social:
Pages:  ..   .. 
Items:  .. 

Navigation

General: Atom Feed Atom Feed  .. 
Help:  ..   .. 
Category:  ..   .. 
Media:  ..   .. 
Posts:  ..   ..   .. 

Statistics

Page:  .. 
Summary:  .. 
1 Tags
10/10 Page Rank
5 Page Refs
1s Time