Let X be a set of sets none of which are empty. Then a choice function ( selector, selection) on X is a mathematical function f that is defined on X such that f is a mapping that assigns each element of X to one of its elements.
An example
Let
X = { {1,4,7}, {9}, {2,7} }. Then the function
f defined by
f({1, 4, 7}) = 7,
f({9}) = 9 and
f({2, 7}) = 2 is a choice function on
X.
History and importance
Ernst Zermelo (1904) introduced choice functions as well as the axiom of choice (AC) and proved the well-ordering theorem,
which states that every set can be
well ordering. AC states that every set of nonempty sets has a choice function. A weaker form of AC, the axiom of countable choice (AC
ω) states that every
countable set of nonempty sets has a choice function. However, in the absence of either AC or AC
ω, some sets can still be shown to have a choice function.
-
If is a finite set set of nonempty sets, then one can construct a choice function for by picking one element from each member of This requires only finitely many choices, so neither AC or ACω is needed.
-
If every member of is a nonempty set, and the union is well-ordered, then one may choose the least element of each member of . In this case, it was possible to simultaneously well-order every member of by making just one choice of a well-order of the union, so neither AC nor ACω was needed. (This example shows that the well-ordering theorem implies AC. The converse is also true, but less trivial.)
Choice function of a multivalued map
Given two sets
and
, let
be a multivalued map from
to
(equivalently,
is a function from
to the
power set of
).
A function is said to be a selection of , if:
The existence of more regular choice functions, namely continuous or measurable selections is important in the theory of differential inclusions, optimal control, and mathematical economics. See Selection theorem.
Bourbaki tau function
Nicolas Bourbaki used
epsilon calculus for their foundations that had a
symbol that could be interpreted as choosing an object (if one existed) that satisfies a given proposition. So if
is a predicate, then
is one particular object that satisfies
(if one exists, otherwise it returns an arbitrary object). Hence we may obtain quantifiers from the choice function, for example
was equivalent to
.
However, Bourbaki's choice operator is stronger than usual: it's a global choice operator. That is, it implies the axiom of global choice.[John Harrison, "The Bourbaki View" eprint.] Hilbert realized this when introducing epsilon calculus.["Here, moreover, we come upon a very remarkable circumstance, namely, that all of these transfinite axioms are derivable from a single axiom, one that also contains the core of one of the most attacked axioms in the literature of mathematics, namely, the axiom of choice: , where is the transfinite logical choice function." Hilbert (1925), “On the Infinite”, excerpted in Jean van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel, p. 382. From nCatLab.]
See also
-
Axiom of countable choice
-
Axiom of dependent choice
-
Hausdorff paradox
-
Hemicontinuity
Notes